逻辑问题 (The Problem of Logic)
(Ke
Ping [Ed.], 2002-2021)
2.1.1.1 Hypothetical syllogism (假言三段论)
2.1.1.2 Disjunctive syllogism (选言三段论)
2.1.1.3 Categorical syllogism (直言三段论)
2.1.2 Fallacy of the consequent (后件推断谬误)
2.1.2.1 Denial of the antecedent (否定前件)
2.1.2.2 Affirmation of the consequent (肯定后件)
2.1.3 Fallacy of illicit major (or minor) premise
(推理前提非法错误)
2.1.3.1 The formation of a categorical syllogism
2.1.3.2 Five basic rules governing the validity of
categorical syllogisms
2.1.3.3 Distribution of terms (周延)
2.1.4 Extended discussion on
correct forms of or rules for syllogistic reasoning
2.1.4.1 Distinction between a
valid deduction (推断) and a valid argument (论断)
2.1.4.2 Verification (证实) vs falsification (证伪)
2.2 Informal Logical
Fallacies
(1) Non sequitur (< Latin: it does not follow 推不出)
(2) Oversimplification (过份简单化)
(3) Hasty generalization (以偏概全;妄下定论)
(4) Argument from dubious authority (诉诸可疑权威)
(5) Begging the question (以假定作为论据来辩论;未经讨论就认为某一有待证明的论点或主张正确;武断;also called Circular Argument 循环论证)
(6) Argument ad hominem (< Latin, against the man 人身攻击)
(7) Argument from ignorance (因缺乏反证而得出结论)
(8) Post hoc ergo propter hoc (< Latin, after this, therefore because of
this 发生于其后者必然是其结果)
(10) Card-stacking (洗牌作弊;片面举证)
(11) Arguing by analogy (比喻式论证)
2.2.2 Fallacies of ambiguity (verbal fallacies)
?
In translating the following sentence from
Chinese into English in the 1999 National Grade 8 Test for English Majors (TEM-8):
?/
Logic is no guarantee that we will not make mistakes in argument. But it will help us to avoid making obvious or absurd mistakes because some ways of reasoning are evidently more fallible than others.
?
In Aristotles formal logic, two ways of reasoning are distinguished, i.e. deductive reasoning or deduction, and inductive reasoning or induction.
A
classic form of deductive reasoning is syllogism,
that is, (a reasoned argument in which
there are two statements which must lead to a third statement). A typical syllogism is a
three-step form like this:
■ All trees have roots. (Major premise)
A plane is a tree. (Minor premise)
Therefore, a plane has roots. (Conclusion)
Few writers arrange their statements in
this strict form, favored by Aristotle in his Rhetoric, a classical
guide to argument so brilliant that it remains useful today. And yet all of us
still employ, at times, the same method of reasoning found in a syllogism: deductive
reasoning. This kind of
reasoning begins with a statement of general truth (All trees have roots) and
moves to a statement about an individual (A plane has roots).
But you might argue the other way around. If instead of starting with a general statement (All trees have roots.), you were to study a score of different trees, find them all having roots, and then conclude that trees have roots, you would follow the opposite method: inductive reasoning. Inductive reasoning is (sometimes called scientific method.) Scientists commonly work in this way: by observing particulars and then drawing general conclusions. In this way new knowledge is acquired about nature.
Either method of reasoning is only as trustworthy as the
observations on which it is based.
Case: Anselmus ontological proof of the existence of God
11世纪修道士安瑟伦 [Anselmus1033-1109106010781093 [investiture: mass noun the action of formally investing a person with honours or rank (NOECD)] 1107(.)] 对上帝存在作了本体论论证 { (St. Thomas Aquinas, 1225-1274) (Wiiliam Perry, 1743-1805) (Kant Immanuel, 1724-1804) :
1. 我们只能把上帝设想成一个无限的、最完美的东西。
2. 一个具有除存在以外的所有完美性(公正、全知、全能等)的东西不能算是最完美的。
3. 因此,最完美的东西 {上帝} 必然存在。
此论证意味着仅仅通过逻辑就可以从我们关于上帝的观念中推出上帝必然存在的结论。果真如此的话,信仰上帝就成了一种严格建立在逻辑基础上的理性信仰。
不用说,许多哲学家都对这种逻辑提出了质疑(即使他们本人也许对其结论深信不疑)。这其中最著名的要算是伊曼努尔康德了。
Test yourself: If you were Kant, how would you challenge Anselmus
ontological proof of Gods existence and what might be your way of proving the
existence of God?
Answer:
?
].
In Zen and the
Art of Motorcycle Maintenance, Robert M.
Pirsig gives memorable short illustrations of the two kinds of reasoning:
[a patch of raised road]
?/
In modern times, a simple, practical method of reasoning has been devised by the British philosopher Stephen Toulmin in The Uses of Argument (Cambridge University Press, 1969). Helpfully, Toulmin has divided a typical argument into three parts:
1. The data, or evidence to prove something
2. The claim, what you are proving with the data
3. The warrant, the thinking that leads from data to claim
Any clear, explicit argument has to have all three parts. Toulmins own example of such an argument is this:
Tommy was born in
(Data) | (Claim)
|
Since Bermuda is a British colony in NW
(Warrant)
(Toulmin, 1969. [The Uses of Argument].
Cambridge University Press)
In arguments we hear or read, we often detect logical fallacies, i.e. common mistakes in thinking or reasoning, or more precisely, a mistake made in the process of moving from the premises of an argument to the conclusion. When we argue by ourselves, we may also inadvertently commit logical fallacies from time to time. As a result of the fallacy, the premises do not justify the conclusion. (Kennedy, X.J. & Dorothy M. Kennedy, 1987, p. 280. [The Bedford Guide for College Writers. NY: St Martins Press.])
In the following we list some most frequently committed logical fallacies with a view to helping you to recognize them when you read or hear them and to guard against them when you make arguments in your own speech and writing. (Some arguments can exhibit more than one fallacy at once.)
Basically, there are three types of logical fallacy:
1. Formal Logical Fallacies (推断形式上的错误)
2. Informal Logical Fallacies (推断内容上的错误)
3. Mixed Logical Fallacies
Formal logical fallacies are mistakes in which the argument violates a rule of the logical system of which that argument is a part. They are classified into:
1. Fallacy of the consequent
a Denial of the antecedent
b Affirmation of the consequent
2. Fallacy of illicit major (or minor) premise
Formal logical fallacies occur when an inference maker
violates any rule governing the validity of a syllogism, so before
characterizing formal logical fallacies, we need to take a closer look at
syllogism.
Syllogism
is a mode of argument that forms the core of the body of Western logical
thought. Aristotle defined syllogistic logic, and his formulations were thought
to be the final word in logic; they underwent only minor revisions in the
subsequent 2,200 years. Every syllogism is a sequence of three propositions
such that the first two imply [(of a fact or occurrence) suggest (something) as a logical
consequence: The forecasted traffic increase implied more roads and more
air pollution. (NOECD) 必然包含; 暗示为必然结果] the
third, the conclusion.
There are three basic types of syllogism: hypothetical, disjunctive, and
categorical.
The hypothetical
syllogism (modus ponens) has as
its first premise a conditional hypothesis:
If p then q; it continues: p, therefore q, e.g.
■ If there is life on Mars [p],
then Mars has an atmosphere [q].
It is
the case that there is life on Mars [p].
Therefore,
it is the case that Mars has an atmosphere [q].
It
should be noted that in the conditional hypothesis, term p presupposes [To require or involve necessarily as an antecedent condition (AHD4)] term q.
Only when this condition is met, can the syllogism be true in both its positive
form and negative form. The negative form and its example are displayed in the
following:
If p, then q;
it is not the case that q; therefore, it is not the case
that p, e.g.
■ If there is life on Mars [p],
then Mars has an atmosphere [q].
It is
not the case that Mars has an atmosphere [q].
Therefore,
it is not the case that there is life on Mars [p].
The disjunctive
syllogism (modus tollens) has as
its first premise a statement of alternatives:
Either p or q;
it continues: not q, therefore p.
The categorical
syllogism comprises three categorical propositions, which must be
statements of the form
all Ss are Ps,
no S is P,
some S is P,
or
some S is not P.
(Based on Syllogism. [2004]. In Columbia Encyclopaedia [
This fallacy (also known as Aristotles fallacy of the
consequent) occurs when the inference maker violates the rule for making a
hypothetical syllogism (If
p then q; it continues: p,
therefore q). It has two forms:
Mistakenly arguing from the
premises If p, then q and not p (symbolized ~ p1) to
the conclusion not q, e.g.
■ *If George is a man of good faith, he can be entrusted with this office; but George is not a man of good faith; therefore, George cannot be entrusted with this office.
{Comment: Not p,
then not q cannot be
deduced from If p, then q because in the conditional hypothesis in a hypothetical
syllogism, term p is one of the many possible conditions conducive to, instead
of a necessary precondition for, term q. Cannot see what is wrong with
that? Look at a more obvious example:
*如果我有电动车,我就能去学校;
可是我没有电动车;
所以我不能去学校。}
Mistakenly arguing from the premises If p, then q and q
to the conclusion p, e.g.
■ *If Amos was a prophet, then he had a social conscience;
Amos had a social conscience; hence,
Amos was a prophet.
{Comment: If q, then p cannot be deduced from If p, then q because in the conditional hypothesis in a hypothetical syllogism, term p, as we noted above, is one of the many possible conditions conducive to, instead of a necessary precondition for, term q.}
This fallacy occurs when the inference maker violates any
one of the five basic rules governing the validity of categorical
syllogisms.
Traditional Aristotelian logic is
concerned with syllogistic reasoning, a form of deductive argument. A syllogism
is an argument made up of propositions [statements 命题] in one of four forms:
Every S is P. (universal affirmative);
No S is P. (universal negative);
Some S is P. (particular affirmative); or
Some S is not P. (particular negative).
The letters stand for common nouns, such
as dog, four-footed animal, living thing, which are called the terms of the
syllogism. S is called the subject term (S, [判断的] 主词/主项), and P, the predicate (P, [判断的] 谓词/谓项), of the syllogism.
A categorical syllogism contains
precisely three terms: the major term (大项), which is the predicate of the conclusion; the minor term (小项), the subject of the conclusion; and the middle term (中项), which appears in both premises but not in the
conclusion. Thus:
■ All men [middle term] are
mortal [major term], [Major
premise]
all philosophers [minor term] are men [middle term]; therefore [Minor premise]
all philosophers [minor term] are mortal [major term]. [Conclusion]
The premises containing the major and
minor terms are named the major and
minor premises (大前提和小前提), respectively.
Aristotle discovered five
basic rules governing the validity of categorical syllogisms:
(1) The middle term must be distributed at least once (a term is said to be distributed [周延] when it refers to all members of the denoted class, as in All S are P and No S is P; see 2.1.3.3 in the following for a more detailed explanation).
(2) A
term distributed in the conclusion must be distributed in the premise in which
it occurs.
(3) Two negative premises imply no valid conclusion.
(4) If one premise is negative, then the conclusion must be negative.
(5) Two affirmatives imply an affirmative.
(Based on Syllogism. [2004]. In Columbia Encyclopaedia [
In syllogistics [三段论式], the application of a term of a proposition to the entire class that the
term denotes. A term is said to be distributed when reference is made to
all members of the class.
Briefly, only universal propositions distribute their
subject term (S, [判断的]主词), and only negative propositions distribute their predicate (P, [判断的] 谓词). {肯定一类事物必须能肯定其全体,而否认一类事物只要举出一个反例即可。}
Naturally, singular terms [singular: Logic Of or relating to the specific as distinguished from the
general; individual.【逻辑学】单称的 (AHD)] (including proper names used as
singular terms) are always distributed, for they refer only to one object and
cannot refer to fewer.
Test yourself: What terms are
distributed and what are not?
What terms in the following forms of proposition are distributed and what
are not?
1) Every
S is P.
2) No
S is P.
3) Some
S is P.
4) Some
S is not P.
Discuss both the subject term (主词) and the predicate (谓词) in each proposition.
Answer:
?
?/
The importance of distribution lies in
its being a principle of formal inference (specifically, the second rule governing the well-formedness of a
categorical syllogism) that no term may be distributed in the conclusion unless it
was distributed in the premises. (Based on Distribution. In BCD 2002)
The illicit major (or minor) premise
fallacy arises when a major (or minor) term that is undistributed in the
premise is distributed in the conclusion, e.g.
■ *All tubers are high-starch foods;
no squashes are tubers;
therefore, no squashes are high-starch
foods.
Analysis:
■ *All tubers are high-starch foods; [undistributed: reference is made to high-starch foods in terms of their quality of having much starch, not of their totality.] [Cf. Every S is P.]
no squashes are tubers;
therefore, no squashes are high-starch foods. [distributed: reference is made to any kind of high-starch food (no squash is high-starch food of whatever kind).] [Cf. No S is P.]
(Based on Distribution. In
Blackburn, Simon 2000. [Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy. 上海:上海外语教育. ix + 418 pp.]; Distribution. In BCD 2002,
and MERL 2004.)
Test yourself: What is it that makes Twains
apology funny?
Mark Twain once remarked to the press that some American congressmen are bastards. That, of course, made some congressmen mad. They pressured Twain to make a public apology. By way of apology, Twain said: some American congressmen are not bastards. What is it that makes Twains apology funny?
Analysis:
?
?/
Conclusion:
?
?/
Test yourself: What would have Twain said if he
had sincerely wished to apologize?
What form of
syllogistic reasoning would Twain have used if he had sincerely wished to
apologize to the congressmen he had cursed earlier?
Answer:
?
?/
Deduction A √
■ All the planets in our solar system are equipped with an atmosphere.
Pluto is a planet in our solar system.
נTherefore, Pluto is equipped with an atmosphere. {Valid deduction, but wrong argument.}
Whether an argument is a valid argument is determined by
the truth or falsity of the content of its premises. Deduction A is
invalid, but Argument A is false because its major premise is false. It is one
of the informal logical fallacies (Fallacies of relevance―the claims made by
the premises are wrong or irrelevant to the truth of the conclusion), which we
will discuss later.
Deduction B /span>
■ *Some animals [middle
term, undistributed; Cf. Some
S is P.] are two-footed.
All
people are animals [middle term, undistributed; Cf. Every S is P.].
√ Therefore, all
people are two-footed. {Sound argument, but invalid deduction.}
Whether an argument is a valid deduction is
determined by its form. This deduction is invalid because it violated
the first basic rule governing the validity of categorical syllogism,
i.e.
(1) The
middle term must be distributed at least once.
An
experiment in scientific research (in principle) allows the researcher to check
against the hypothesis and say this hypothesis is right. If so, the experiment
supports (or verifies) the hypothesis and the researcher is
justified in adding the idea behind the hypothesis to their theoretical base.
If,
on the other hand, the experiment says this hypothesis is wrong, this would be falsifying
the hypothesis.
Case: What is the logical basis of Poppers famous
argument that one can never totally verify a theory?
The importance that scientists have attached to falsification (as opposed to verification) goes back to the 1930s,
when Karl Popper [1902-1994. Austrian-born British
philosopher of science, known for his theory of scientific method and for his
criticism of historical determinism] developed our current view of how theories are created and
re-created.
According to
Popper, it is possible to overturn a theory, but it is impossible to make it
absolutely correct. In Poppers terms you can never totally verify (prove) a
theorybut you can falsify it with one conflicting observation.
What is the
logical basis of Poppers famous argument that one can never totally verify a
theory?
(Based on
Goodman, Albert. [School of Computing and Mathematics, Deakin University,
Australia] [1996]. Introduction to Data Collection and Analysis.)
Test yourself: What is wrong with
verification?
Analysis:
?
?/
Test yourself: How should we find out the
scientific validity of the theory of translation universals?
The theory of translation universals developed by Mona Baker
and others has concerned a number of scholars in the international translation
community in the past decade or so. How should we find out the scientific
validity of this theory?
Analysis:
?
?/
Informal logical
fallacies are
mistakes caused by wrong, irrelevant or ambiguous evidence. They are classified
into:
1. Fallacies
of relevance
2. Fallacies
of ambiguity (verbal fallacies)
Fallacies of relevance are those arguments in which the truth of the
conclusion does not depend on the claims made by the premises; in other words,
the claims made by the premises are wrong or irrelevant to the truth of the
conclusion. The
following are some familiar fallacies of relevance:
■ Non
sequitur
■ Oversimplification
■ Hasty generalization
■ Argument from dubious authority
■ Begging the question
■ Argument ad hominem
■ Argument from ignorance
■ Post hoc
ergo propter hoc
■ Stereotypes
■ Card-stacking
■ Arguing by analogy
Stating a claim
that doesnt follow from the (minor) premise (or the statement you begin with),
because the major premise is false.
■ Jergus will make an excellent
husband for Marge. Why, in high school he got all As.
■ In order to greet National Day,
Beijing is carrying out various renovations. Many renovated buildings belong to
the so-called "bean dregs or shoddy project. Because of the limited time,
those projects have to be finished in a hurry. So though the government calls
on the builders to pay attention to quality, many new or renewed bean dregs
projects still kept appearing irresistibly. (Students essay)
■ The cover of a 1997 Beijing
Youth Weekly has Chinese Defeat Kasparov! splashed across a picture of the
downcast grand master. Two of the six members of the IBM research group that
programmed Deep Blue, it turns out, were Chinese-Americans. It was the genius
of these two Chinese, one article asserts, that allowed Deep Blue to defeat Mr.
Kasparov. (Peter Hays Gries. 2003. China's New Nationalism: Pride,
Politics, and Diplomacy. A Philip E.
Lilienthal Book in Asian Studies. The University of California Press.
Retrieved December 22, 2004, from http://www.ucpress.edu/books/pages/9662/9662.intro.html)
■ 收到过坏人送的匾的人一定自己不是东西
李敖攻击诗人余光中(就是那位著名的乡愁诗的作者),理由如下:余光中70岁生日的时候,国民党主席、混蛋李登辉赠他一个匾连珠缀玉。请大家去想好了,你不是个拍马屁,你不是个马屁精,为什么有李登辉这种货色的人送匾给你。可见你是什么东西啊!
(Retrieved October 16, 2006, from
http://blog.sina.com.cn/u/48670cb20100062a)
A special kind of
non-sequitur fallacy―reversing cause and effect or taking cause for effect [倒因为果]):
■ Bob is well trained, therefore
Bob is an astronaut.
■ 我们将英语翻译分为两类:汉译英和英译汉。其实,在中国英语学习者的思维角度上,语言在大脑的思维过程正是这两类的不断应用。由于我国的教育体制尚为应试教育,所以,这两类之间的运用更始根深蒂固,说白了,如果能灵活地运用汉译英和英译汉,语言水平将会有质的飞跃! (机械工业出版社时代金科编辑室约稿函)
Supplying neat and
easy explanations for large and complicated phenomena (Cf. Albert Einsteins famous quotepaying special attention to
the second half of this quote: everything should be made as simple as possible,
but not one bit simpler.).
■ We have a lot of unemployment now
in this country because people are too lazy to work.
■ If we want to do away with drug
abuse, lets get tough: lets sentence every drug user to death.
A special kind of
oversimplified thinkingEither/or reasoning [assuming that a
reality may be divided into only two parts, that there are only two sides to a
question, that all statements are either true or false, that all questions
demand either a yes or a no answer.]:
■ What are we going to do about
acid rain? Either we shut down all the factories that cause it, or we just
forget about acid rain and learn to live with it. Weve got no choice, right?
■ 中山陵雨花台门票上涨成定局
昨天,在南京市物价局组织的价格调整听证会上,21名来自社会各界的听证代表一致同意上调两陵价格。
此次,中山陵景区申请把25元的门票上升到40元;雨花台申请从15元调至25元。
南京市人大代表、中山大厦工会主席周敏华认为,据统计,两陵的游客95%是外地人,由于门票相对便宜,因此一到长假中山陵的游客骤增,最多一天达10万人次,远远超过了景区的承受能力,极不利于景区的品牌形象。因此,提高价格可以缓解人流量,有利于景区的可持续发展。
(《新华日报》2002年11月29日1版)
The assumption
that what is true of a few cases is true in general.
Example 1.
■ Bertrand Russells cruel example:
the chickens hasty generalization that the farmwifes coming means food.
Example 2.
■ But thats not my dog.
The practice of
defending a conclusion by appealing to force, pity, authority, or popular
belief.
■ According to some of the most
knowing scientists in America, smoking two packs a day is as harmless as eating
a couple of oatmeal cookies.
■ According to some of the most
famous scientists in China, eating our pills will help short men to grow taller
within a few days.
■ 腰酸背疼腿抽筋请服巨能钙;买好钙巨能钙;8位博士、48位科学家、{Who were they?} 100项科学实践、10年呕心沥血,终于研究出一种产品那就是巨能钙。
:
Defending a
conclusion by appealing to popular belief is known as Bandwagon
appeals, i.e. using the desire to go along with the crowd as fact:
■ Surveys show that a majority of the people
want only family oriented programming on television. Therefore, this must be
our goal.
Setting out to
prove a statement that is already taken for granted (or, in other words,
assuming in the premises what is to be proved).
This fallacy
sometimes takes the form of tautology or arguing in a circle (i.e.
stating or believing a fact to be its own reason).
■ He is a liar because he simply is not
telling the truth.
■ Most people like gardening because it is
something they enjoy.
■ Its wet because it has water on it.
■ I know because I know.
Attacking peoples
opinions by attacking their character.
■ Jack may argue that we need to save the
whales, but Jack is the kind of person who always gets excited over nothing.
■ Jack would have us spend millions to save
whales, but I happen to know that he owns a yacht from which he selfishly
enjoys watching whales.
■ 西方翻译理论家对于普遍性的诉求和具有的广阔的 [学术研究] 视野,同时不也反映了他们与生俱来的种族优越感吗?(《中国翻译》2002年第2期第5页)
{Comment: 此论还犯有常识性错误:当今国际翻译界有影响的理论家,很多原籍甚至现籍都并非欧美,人也并非金发碧眼的优秀民族的成员。}
Maintaining that,
because a conclusion has not been disproved, it has to be accepted or, because
a conclusion has not been proved, it should be rejected.
■ Despite years of effort, no one has
conclusively proved that ghosts dont exist; therefore, we should expect to see
them at any time.
■ No one has ever shown that there is
intelligent life on any other planet. Evidently the notion of visitors from
other planets in the universe is unthinkable.
Confusing cause
and effect.
■ Because the new Premier of
Russia sent a rose to every woman member of the Duma as a token of his
gratitude for their support of the work of his government, he was soon
dismissed from office by President Yeltzin.
■ The devastating earthquake which
struck Taiwan recently was a warning sent by Heaven to Li Denghui, since it
occurred shortly after Li made another attempt to split China by claiming
statehood for Taiwan.
Both positive and
negative ones should be avoided.
■ Being a woman meant she was smaller than a
man.
■ Being a woman meant she was more
compassionate than a man.
Ignoring an
issues contrary evidence.
■ A pro-gun paper that cites only people who
have used guns to protect themselves from danger, or an anti-gun paper that
cites only accidental deaths caused by guns.
Using a metaphor as
though it were evidence.
In logic, analogy
is the name of an inductive form of argument which asserts that if two or more
entities are similar in one or more respects, then a probability exists that
they will be similar in other respects.
An analogy explains
a complicated idea in terms of something familiar: for instance, shooting a
spacecraft to another planet is like placing a golf ball with uncanny accuracy
into a hole half a mile away and a risky action is analogized to 盲人骑瞎马,夜半临深池 in Chinese.
■ People were born as free as the birds. Its
wrong and cruel to expect them to work.
■ [In 1633, Scipio Chiaramonti, professor of
philosophy at the University of Pisa, argued against Galileo:] Animals, which
move, have limbs and muscles. The earth has no limbs and muscles, hence it does
not move.
■ [江苏经济台保险全接触节目(平安保险公司赞助)广告]现代生活离不开保险,就像生命离不开水、阳光和空气。
■ [街头广告]买X,做真正的男人/女人!
Fallacies of ambiguity (verbal fallacies) are erroneous conclusions based on the
equivocal use of language.
■ All laws are the
product of legislative activity. Newton discovered several laws;
therefore, Newton discovered several products of legislative activity.
■ [CCTV-1 advertisement featuring 唐国强]
Shot 1 唐国强:买保险就是买平安
Shot 2 Slogan:中国平安(保险)
(Partly based on Kennedy, X.J.
& Dorothy M. Kennedy [1987] [The
Bedford Guide for College Writers. NY: St Martins Press.])
Mixed logical
fallacies refer
to cases in which formal and informal fallacies co-exist in an inference.
Case: 工人都没看过的书农民也不会看
2003年年底,安徽作家陈桂棣、吴春桃(南大中文系毕业生)夫妇历经三年创作的报告文学《中国农民调查》,在《当代》杂志第6期上发表了。由于作品深刻地揭示了当前三农问题面临的诸多难题和矛盾,真实地反映了农民的心声,因此在读者中引起了强烈共鸣。2004年元月,《中国农民调查》一书由人民文学出版社出版,在一个多月的时间内就发行了近十万册。2004年该书荣获尤里西斯国际报导文学奖。2004年10月20日南大中文系请他们来做演讲。演讲结束后一个同学的提问是:我问一个在合肥市工厂里工作的朋友有没有看过你们的书。他都说没看过。请问还会有农民看你们的书吗?陈桂棣说:这个问题没法回答。不但我们没法回答,就是统计局也没法回答。
What logical
fallacies can you identify in the students bewildering question?
Analysis:
?
?/
Case: 不支持议会政治者不是思想家
李敖认为鲁迅不是思想家,证明过程如下:
在新文化运动的时候,五四时代,所谓提倡的德先生和赛先生,赛先生是科学,德先生是民主,可是鲁迅反对议会政治,请问反对议会政治的人,怎么能够提倡民主呢?如果民主没有议会,这叫什么民主呢?这表示说,鲁迅基本的社会科学常识,政治学的常识都不及格,而这种人怎么能够像毛泽东所说的是思想家呢? (Retrieved October 16, 2006,
from http://blog.sina.com.cn/u/48670cb20100062a)
What logical
fallacies can you identify in Li Aos argument?
Analysis:
?
?/
(Page updated: June, 2011; March
2012; May, 2012; June, 2015; June, 2016; May, 2017; April, 2019; May, 2020)